Since I’ve stated in STALKING THE PERFECT TERM: THE THREE PROBABILITIES that it was a mistake to invoke the
concept of coherence in respect to probability, I should hold forth on the
original context of the concept.
I articulated
the concept in response to Susanne Langer’s useful distinction between
“discursive symbolism” and “presentational symbolism” in her 1942 book PHILOSOPHY IN A NEW KEY. Langer did
not say anything about judging particular literary manifestations of these two forms of
symbolism. In contrast, I wanted to expound on ways in which these very different
symbolic discourses could be used competently or not so competently. So the argument came down to two
interdependent parts:
(1) A well-known
trope, like Batman- villains placing the Crusader in a death-trap rather than
simply shooting him, was not a worthless endeavor simply because it flew in the
face of logical, discursive symbolism.
Patently the death-trap had a function even if it was one that couldn’t
be justified discursively: the device served to test the ability of Batman—or a
similar hero in similar dire straits—for the enjoyment of the reader. Hence it was justifiable in terms of Langer’s
“presentational symbolism,” having no more connection with logical discourse than
a symphonic piece.
(2) The second
part was my own idea: that even though the trope of the death-trap could not be
critiqued on the basic of logic, it could be critiqued aesthetically: as to
whether it communicated a certain effect.
In GESTURE AND GESTALT PART 3 I showed why one death-trap was coherent and expressive while
another one was not.
The corresponding essay PART 4
argued that the same principle of coherence should apply to tropes that were
intended to be discursively meaningful, and I gave examples of, respectively,
coherent and incoherent manifestations of discursive symbolism.
I now perceive that by I linked the
concept of coherence to the NUM formula
because I formed an unconscious link between the very different ways in
which Langer and C.S. Lewis spoke of “presentation.”
In NEW KEY Langer used the term to distinguish an aspect
of human perception: to underscore that when humans were presented with
sense-experiences, they did not ipso facto interpret them with respect to discursive
symbolic models.
In THE PROBLEM OF PAIN, though, C.S. Lewis spoke of
“realism of presentation” as a socially constructed discourse, which is to say
one that *was * informed by a given reader’s expectations as to what or was not
believable in a logical and discursive sense.
I now surmise that when Lewis spoke of “realism of content,” I lined up this conceptualization with that of Tzvetan Todorov’s idea of "the marvelous," that category of all fictions that represented something “unreal” as being “real,” rather like Aristotle’s “probable impossibility.”
Similarly, I’ve repeatedly claimed, in my rewrite of Todorov, that the differences between “the naturalistic” and “the uncanny” depend not on the reader’s perceptions of the narrative, as Todorov had it, but on the way in which an author “presents” a trope like, say, “psychotic madman on the rampage.”
Todorov wished to assert that whatever was not cognitively unreal was perforce “real.” I assert that the category of “the uncanny” depended on an affective factor—the presence of “strangeness”—that allied that category with that of the marvelous, so that both were categories of the metaphenomenal.
From there, I unfortunately tried
to bring in the other half of Aristotle’s famous dictum, the “possible
improbability,” and judge it not by “possibility” but by coherence—hence the
“coherent probability” (for the uncanny) and the “incoherent probability” for
the naturalistic. But the use of
probability and/or possibility, whether invoked by Lewis or by Aristotle, are
not determinative, because they depend on socially constructed criteria as to
what is possible or probable. As I noted in PROBABILITY SHIFTS, the nature of probability
depends on the ground rules of a given fictional cosmos, and those ground rules
are created not by expectations external to the work but by the way in which
the work’s author constructs the cognitive and affective aspects of the work—to
which I will turn next.
No comments:
Post a Comment